Unitarian
Universalist Association
General Assembly, Rochester, N.Y.
June 27, 1998
Unitarian
Universalism in Societal Perspective
Robert N. Bellah
Let me start by
telling you who I am in a little more detail than as coauthor of Habits of the
Heart and The Good Society. I am a trinitarian Episcopalian with a strong
ecclesiology. But I also have some enduring associations with your
tradition. James Luther Adams was my mentor when I first started
teaching-I was one-third time in the Harvard Divinity School. It was Jim
who introduced me to much of the "lore," as he called it, of the social
history of Christianity. Conrad Wright, whose recent book on UU polity I
have enjoyed reading, was also my colleague at HDS in those days. Through
my involvement with the Graduate Theological Union in Berkeley, I have had a
long-term relation to the Starr King School for the Ministry, where one of my
ablest former students, Clare Fischer, teaches. Most recently I have been
associated with Denny Davidoff on the board of the Interfaith Alliance
Foundation.
To put it more
abstractly, while I am rather far from you theologically (I actually hope to use
my trinitarian Christianity as well as my sociology to gain an outsider
perspective on your movement), I am in solid agreement with your social witness:
your opposition to racism, your inclusiveness, not only with respect to race but
also with respect to gender and sexual orientation, and your strong stance on
issues of economic and social justice. The resolution entitled "Working
for a Just Economic Community," which you passed at your General Assembly a
year ago, even though it was printed in very small print in the World, seems
admirable to me in every clause.
I want to begin
with a provocative paradox that contains in germ everything I want to say
tonight: in your social witness you are strong dissenters, especially in
terms of economic trends in today's America; but religiously and therefore
culturally, you are mainstream, right at the American center. How can that
be? you will say. Didn't Jim Adams put us squarely in the tradition of
religious dissent and hasn't our whole tradition been one of religious dissent
from beginning to end? Yes he did and it has been. The problem is
that the majority of American religions have been in the dissenting tradition.
Seymour Martin Lipset points out that ours is the only North Atlantic society
where dissenting denominations have been in the majority through most if its
history. All other North Atlantic societies have had a tradition of an
established church.
What does it mean
to be a dissenter in a society with a religious majority of dissenters? It
certainly doesn't mean that the dissenters agree. They are much too busy
dissenting from each other. You may say, haven't the Southern Baptists,
even though they come from the largest group of American dissenters, shown of
late an alarming tendency toward authoritarianism? And indeed they have.
But we should remember that even the bizarre statement from their general
convention in Salt Lake City earlier this month on the position of women in the
family (how can you caricature people who caricature themselves better than any
outsider could do?) had no authority over any congregation or any member
of any congregation. Their polity is as strictly congregational and their
religion as strongly individualistic as yours. In the face of the
dissenting majority in America, perhaps dissent at a deeper level is represented
by the battered remnants of the establishment tradition: Catholics,
Episcopalians, Lutherans, Presbyterians, though even they, in their minority
status, are tempted to become sectarian. As Chesterton said, in America
even the Catholics are Protestant.
Just to rub in my
point that religiously UUs are part of the majority let me point out that one of
your deepest beliefs, that in matters of religion the individual conscience must
be unfettered, is shared by a majority of Americans. As we noted in Habits
of the Heart, according to a Gallup poll 80 percent of Americans agreed that
"an individual should arrive at his or her own religious beliefs independent
of any churches or synagogues," a rather amazing idea when you think about it.
I have studied
carefully the very rewarding report of your Commission on Appraisal published
last year as Interdependence: renewing congregational polity, and I know
that the central purpose of the Fulfilling the Promise initiative is to
strengthen a sense of connectedness, interdependence, and community, partly to
counterbalance a perceived excessive emphasis on individualism. I simply
want to point out that, starting from where you start, it may not be so easy to
get there from here. In order to describe your religious individualism
more carefully I will draw on the statement of Principles and Purposes that you
adopted in 1985, the survey conducted by the Fulfilling the Promise Committee,
and from the whole history of your movement.
The very first of
the principles affirmed in your 1985 statement is "The inherent worth and
dignity of every person." In an essay to be published this fall in the
Journal of the American Academy of Religion entitled "Is There a Common
American Culture?" I answer that yes, there is a common culture, and that its
most fundamental tenet is the sacredness of the individual conscience, the
individual person. Your opening affirmation therefore places you at the
very center of American culture. That affirmation is reinforced be several
more affirmations: for example, "a free and responsible search for truth
and meaning," and "the right of conscience and the use of the democratic
process within our congregations and in society at large." These
individualistic affirmations are moderated by the two final principles the
document affirms: "the goal of world community with peace, liberty, and
justice for all" and "respect for the interdependent web of all existence of
which we are a part." These affirmations are certainly important in
complementing the individualistic affirmations, but, I will argue that the mere
affirmation of community or even the interdependent web of all existence is not
in itself enough to offset a fundamentally individualistic initial position.
That the emphasis
on individual autonomy is clearly supported by the membership is indicated by
the answers to a number of the survey questions. I will start by
discussing some of those questions that Clark Olsen singled out as drawing
strong majority answers from every demographic sector of the association,
questions that suggest stronger common beliefs within the association than some
had expected. For example, the very first question, "What things should
your congregation be most intent on helping children learn?" was answered by a
70 percent majority by "a sense of their inherent worth, self-respect," a
clear choice for the most individualistic of the possible answers. The
second most popular response, and the one most chosen as "next most
important" was "openness to difference and respect for others." That
seems to suggest a somewhat more social orientation, but I would argue that it
is the thin social extension of our radical individualism. Indeed I
formulated our common creed in my essay as, in the age of multiculturalism:
"we are all different, we are all unique, respect that," which comes pretty
close to "openness to difference and respect for others." The point is
that emphasizing difference and respect for difference leaves us pretty well
adrift when it comes to what could possibly hold us together.
Another question
with an answer that draws a nearly 70 percent majority is "What needs for a
child's religious development could ideally be best served within the
community of UU faith?" to which the majority answer is "A sense of
belonging, along with respect for difference." This question is as
interesting for the way it is formulated as for the strong majority agreement.
One of the problems with surveys as opposed to open-ended interviews is that
they generate the response by the way they are formulated. The
outside observer might have liked two questions here: one about belonging,
one about respect for difference. It is as though the writers of the
question were anxious as to how much appeal "a sense of belonging" would
have without the individualistic caveat "along with respect for difference."
In any case, putting the two phrases together was a winning combination.
Another question
that drew a clear but less overwhelming majority for one answer was "What role
has your congregation played most importantly in your life?" Some 56
percent chose "It supports my views and upholds my values," which I would
take to be an individualistic affirmation of what the congregation is doing for
me. The second most popular answer to this question gives a clear
alternative to the first choice: "It is a beloved community of forgiveness,
love and spiritual growth," and that answer, one that placed the community
first rather than the self, drew 44 percent. These answers suggest that it
is not only in the work of the commission that wrote the Interdependence
document but in the congregations themselves that there is, in spite of the
clear priority of religious individualism, an undercurrent of desire for an
understanding that is fundamentally more social.
The last question
I want to discuss at this point is both encouraging and discouraging from the
point of view I am trying to develop in this talk. It is "What is the
'glue' that binds individual UUs and congregations together?" The 65
percent majority answer was: "Shared values and principles."
That is certainly encouraging for the people who feared that UUs held such
different positions that they shared very little. The most chosen answer
to this question only makes explicit what is implicit in the degree of agreement
in the answers to many questions: UUs do share values and principles.
What is discouraging to me in my wish that UUs and other Americans had a more
fundamentally social understanding of human beings is that though values and
principles are shared all right, what is shared is still fundamentally
individualistic. And the least chosen answer to this question, indeed the
one that over 61 percent said was "least important" was "common worship
elements and language." There may be hidden problems in this
answer that I'm not seeing, but if it means that "common worship" is least
important in what holds UUs together, then my anxiety level does indeed rise.
For it is my understanding as a sociologist of religion that it is common
worship that creates the beloved community for which many UUs yearn.
Furthermore, shared values and principles don't necessarily motivate people to
do anything; whereas a vital experience of common worship can send a
congregation out into the world with a determination to see that those values
and principles are put into practice. Of course I know that in many
congregations today, perhaps even a few UU congregations, worship can be a form
of sanctuary, therapy, even cocooning, which draws people away from the world
rather than motivating them to change the world: it surely all depends on
what kind of worship.
Just to indicate
how deep the issues I am discussing go in UU history, let me turn to Conrad
Wright's book Congregational Polity. He singles out three attitudes that
can be discerned in the mid-19th century: institutionalism, parochialism,
and individualism, and he goes on to say that "To this day, [these
attitudes] remain imperfectly reconciled, often within the minds and hearts of
individual Unitarian Universalists." (p. 68) By individualism he means
the emphasis on the individual seeker, so that the person barely needs the
congregation, much less the denomination. By parochialism he
means the attitude, common enough in all denominations, to consider one's own
local congregation sufficient, so that "the church" comes to mean my church
down by the corner. The document Interdependence quite rightly suggests
that parochialism is only the repeat of radical individualism at the
congregational level. And by institutionalism Wright means a concern for
larger structures and agencies, particularly at the denominational level, which
will facilitate the religious life of congregations and enhance their joint
impact on the world. Neither among UUs nor among other Americans has
institutionalism ever had an easy time, or even a good name, as my coauthors and
I showed in The Good Society. And yet, as we claimed in that book, without
good institutions there will not be good communities and without good
communities there will not be good individuals.
Wright singles out
individuals important in the history of Unitarian universalism as representative
of each of these attitudes, and I want to mention two of them. For
institutionalism he holds up a man after my own heart, Henry W. Bellows.
According to Wright,
basically
[Bellows] argued, Unitarianism revealed the ultimate tendency of Protestantism
to an individualism which was "the self-sufficiency of man" and "an
absolute independence of Bible or church." That tendency had gone as
far as it could, he thought, and a reassertion of the importance of the
corporate nature of human life, in family, state, and church, was indicated.
"Nor is there any complete and satisfactory, perhaps no real way, to come
into this corporate capacity, except through a publicly recognized and
legitimate organization, whether domestic, political, or religious." (p, 43)
Needless to say,
Wright credits Bellows with such an effective institution building that the
Unitarian denomination was able to survive the difficult times that lay ahead in
the late 19th century.
As an example of
the individualist attitude, Wright offers up a pastor with the charming name of
Octavius Brooks Frothingham. "What Frothingham offered in his own
church," says Wright, "was a place where absolute freedom of conscience was
assured both in pulpit and pew."
Frothingham
found that it was the sermon rather than the preliminaries that drew the
crowds; many of his hearers arrived just in time for it. . . [N]owhere
in the life of the society was there either cultivation of the devotional
spirit through sacrament or ritual, or organization to promote cooperation for
human betterment. Frothingham's preaching was what mattered. He was an
effective public speaker with a personal following, enlarged by many curious
casual listeners. In 1879, when ill health made it necessary for him to
give up his preaching, the church disbanded because nothing remained.
(pp. 69-70)
Such is the fate
of a religious individualism totally unleavened by institutionalism.
Now you may well
say, what's wrong with religious individualism as long as there is enough
institutionalism to keep the movement alive but not so much that individuals or
congregations feel pushed around? And here is where I need to sharpen my
argument. Let me begin in a slightly roundabout way. In the May 14
issue of The New York Review of Books Mark Lilla describes two kinds of current
American reaction. We have two kinds of reactionaries, says Lilla, because
we had in our recent history two revolutions. The first was the revolution
of the sixties which was both a cultural and a political revolution, one that
led to greater freedom of personal expression and greater acceptance of groups
that were previously marginalized such as racial minorities, women and gays.
Those in reaction against this revolution emphasize traditional values and
consider the family as the key institution whose strengthening can solve all our
problems. This group explicitly wants to return women and gays to their
traditional place, and by opposing affirmative action, to return racial
minorities to their traditional place, and they would even like to repress
disturbing forms of free expression such as flag burning. The second
revolution was the Reagan revolution of the eighties, an economic but also a
political revolution. Those in reaction against this revolution are
unhappy about the dominance of the free market ideology, the commodification of
just about everything including law, medicine and education, and would like to
restore or even strengthen dismantled features of the welfare state, such as
programs to rebuild our inner cities rather than abandoning them. So far I
think we can all see that Lilla is describing something real. I feel, and
I suspect many of you feel, quite opposed to the first kind of reaction but very
much part of the second kind of reaction. But here comes the bad news:
Lilla says there weren't really two revolutions-there was only one.
The two are deeply and intimately related and the majority of Americans have
embraced them both. Now I don't want to believe that and I suspect many
of you don't want to believe that but I think it is important that we try to
discern what possible truth Lilla may be pointing to.
The revolution of
the sixties did not come from nowhere. I would argue that it was another
stage in the unfolding of what I have already described as our deepest common
value, respect for the individual conscience, the individual person, a respect
that is rooted in our dominant religious tradition of dissenting Protestantism.
But if we look
back to the source of that tradition we will find something that makes Lilla's
argument a little less preposterous. In the article on our common American
culture that I have referred to earlier in this talk, I called to mind the
dissenting tradition. What was so important about the Baptists, and other
sectarians such as the Quakers, was the absolute centrality of religious
freedom, of the sacredness of individual conscience in matters of religious
belief. We generally think of religious freedom as one of many kinds of
freedom, many kinds of human rights, first voiced in the European Enlightenment,
and echoing around the world ever since. But Georg Jellinek, Max Weber's
friend, and, on these matters, his teacher, published a book in 1895 called Die
Erklärung der Menschen- und Bürgerrechte, translated into English in 1901 as
The Declaration of the Rights of Man and of Citizens, which argued that the
ultimate source of all modern notions of human rights is to be found in the
radical sects of the Protestant Reformation, particularly the Quakers and
Baptists. Of this development Weber writes, "Thus the consistent sect
gives rise to an inalienable personal right of the governed as against any
power, whether political, hierocratic or patriarchal. Such freedom of
conscience may be the oldest Right of Man-as Jellinek has argued convincingly,
at any rate it is the most basic Right of Man because it comprises all ethically
conditioned action and guarantees freedom from compulsion, especially from the
power of the state. In this sense the concept was as unknown to antiquity
and the Middle Ages as it was to Rousseau. . . " Weber then goes
on to say that the other Rights of Man were later joined to this basic right,
"especially the right to pursue one's own economic interests, which includes
the inviolability of individual property, the freedom of contract, and
vocational choice." (1978:1209) So, almost from the beginning the
sacredness of conscience, of the individual person was linked to "the right to
pursue one's own economic interests." Remember that Weber locates the
famous "Protestant ethic" in the intersection of Calvinism and sectarianism
out of which our own dissenting tradition comes. Freedom of conscience and
freedom of enterprise are more closely, even genealogically, linked than many of
us would like to believe. As I hope to show, they are both expressions of
an underlying ontological individualism.
So, it is no
accident, as they say, that the United States, with its high evaluation of the
individual person, is nonetheless alone among North Atlantic societies in the
percentage of our population who live in poverty and that we are dismantling
what was already the weakest welfare state of any North Atlantic nation.
Just when we are moving to an ever greater validation of the sacredness of the
individual person, our capacity to imagine a social fabric that would hold
individuals together is vanishing. And this is in no small part due to the fact
that our religious individualism is linked to an economic individualism which,
though it makes no distinctions between persons except monetary ones, ultimately
knows nothing of the sacredness of the individual. If the only standard is
money, then all other distinctions are undermined.
What economic
individualism destroys and what our kind of religious individualism cannot
restore, is solidarity, a sense of being members of the same body. In most
other North Atlantic societies a tradition of an established church, however
secularized, provides some notion that we are in this thing together, that we
need each other, that our precious and unique selves aren't going to make it
all alone. That is a tradition singularly weak in our country, though
Catholics and some high church Protestants have tried to provide it. Nor
do we have a tradition of democratic socialism such as is common in
Europe-again, I would argue, linked to an established church culture-a
tradition that believes the state has some responsibility for the well-being of
its citizens.
So, alas, perhaps
Mark Lilla is right: the cultural revolution and the Reagan revolution are
two sides of the same coin. Radical religio-cultural individualism opens
the door to radical economic individualism. The former provides inadequate
resources to moderate the latter. Here I return to the paradox from which
I started, the contradiction between your social witness and your religious
tradition: in your social witness you are dissenters; in your religious
beliefs you are mainstream in a culture whose majority is dissenters. How
can you possibly gain the religious and cultural leverage to overcome this
contradiction?
Here let me assert
that what religious liberalism and American culture generally lack is a social
understanding of human beings. We start from an ontological individualism,
the idea that individuals are real, society is secondary. This is clear in
the dissenting tradition. Individuals are "called out" of the
established churches; they establish new religious associations. Why do
the Baptists, the largest of the dissenting communions, insist on adult baptism?
Because infants cannot make a decision, cannot choose Jesus Christ as their
personal lord and savior. Only adults who have made that decision can be
baptized and admitted to full communion in the church. The
Congregationalists, from whom the Unitarians derive, did not go quite that far.
They did allow infant baptism, but at least at first, they did not allow full
church membership to any who had not had a conversion experience. In
short, Baptists, Congregationalists and other dissenters, believed individuals
were saved first and then were admitted to membership in the church. In
this understanding it is not the church that gives rise to believers but
believers that give rise to the church.
The same
ontological individualism can be found in the Anglo-American tradition of
secular social philosophy, clearly for example, in John Locke, the most
influential figure, I would argue, in American cultural history, indeed the
spiritual father of us all, whether we like it or not. For Locke,
individuals define themselves initially in relation to nature, making their
livings out of the fruit of the land. Only when they fear for the safety
of their property are they moved through mutual covenant, to form a society for
the common protection of property. Society is derivative; individuals are
fundamental: the common sense of our culture.
I want to assert,
however, that ontological individualism is false both theologically and
sociologically. I am tempted to start my rebuttal with theology, but I
think it wiser in this setting to start with science and reason.
Anglo-American individualism infects everything it touches, even our science.
The notion that we are fundamentally self-interest maximizers, the secular side
of our ontological individualism, has given rise to the movement known as
sociobiology. I can think of no better place to start my
counterattack than the recent book of the Dutch primatologist, Frans de Waal,
Good Natured: The Origins of Right and Wrong in Humans and Other Animals
(Harvard, 1996). De Waal shows that, leaving aside the theory of the
selfish gene (other biologists such as Stephen Gould are showing why that
can't be the whole story about evolution), one cannot go from genetics to
individual motivation. He argues that the presence of generosity to the
point of self-sacrifice, is documented for higher mammals, including not only
our nearest primate relatives, but whales and dolphins as well. According
to de Waal, not only sympathy and nurturing, but even a sense of justice, are
things we share with higher mammals, are part of our nature. As he puts
it:
If group life is
based on a social contract, it is drawn up and signed not by individual
parties, but by Mother Nature. . . Even in our species, which prides
itself on free will, we may find an occasional hermit who has opted for
reclusion; yet we never encounter someone who has consciously decided to
become social. One cannot decide to become what one already is.
(p. 170)
In the Anglo-Saxon
world this comes as news, to some of us very good news. De Waal seems to
be saying to us, "You are not the isolated selfish persons that you think you
are"; "know thyself," or perhaps even better, "Become what you are,"
"Recover your fundamentally social nature." Of course to a
sociologist, this is not exactly news. It was Emile Durkheim who insisted
that society is a reality sui generis and that we only become individuals in and
through society. It was our own American social psychologist George
Herbert Mead who worked this out concretely in the experience of the growing
child. We become a self through, as Mead puts it, internalizing the role
of the other. That moment when an infant takes the spoon out of its
mother's hand, dips it in the food and raises it to the mother's mouth is
the moment when the child through becoming the mother becomes a person, able to
love as well as be loved. Today we might better say "parent" than
"mother," but the point is the same. And if the child is not nurtured,
is abandoned or abused, its sense of self will be irreparably damaged. We
are not born at the age of 21 as autonomous rational beings. We are born
helpless and dependent and only through the love of others will we ever become
autonomous selves. Theologically that could be put "We love because he
first loved us," (1Jn:4,19) but I will discuss theology later. If we are
fundamentally relational creatures, as I think both biology and sociology
affirm, then ontological individualism, religious or secular, is simply a
mistake, but one with enormous cultural consequences with which Americans in
particular will have to deal.
What the document
Interdependence is on the verge of asking, I am forthrightly asking: give
up ontological individualism and affirm that human nature is fundamentally
social. That would mean making "the interdependent web of all
existence" the first of your principles and not the last.
But am I asking
too much; am I asking you to do something that you don't have the resources to
do? I can't answer that question; only you can. But I am saying
that if you believe in "a free and responsible search for truth," the truth
is that our nature is social.
Even though I
can't answer the question, I can discuss what resources I discern that might
help give a positive answer. Let me turn first to the survey, where I find
more than a few indications that a social understanding of UUism is by no means
entirely absent. In answer to the question "How does being a Unitarian
Universalist sustain you in times of crisis, tragedy or pain?" more than 61
percent say "it provides a community of love, support and renewal."
However, for me, for reasons I will come back to, a somewhat worrisome answer to
this question is the low number of people who said "provides a sense of
transcendence, God or a healing power"-only 16 percent put that answer first
and 58 percent put it last. Also, since the question refers to times of
crisis, one might wonder if the 61 percent choosing community mean that it is
only in times of crisis that they need community. My anxiety is allayed,
however by the answer to another question, "What are your dreams for the UU
movement?" where the answer of over 73 percent was "Become a visible and
influential force for good in the world." I take that as a
non-individualistic answer because, first, it comes in the context of the UU
movement, not individual action, and second, being a force for good in the world
is far too difficult to do alone. Any effective work in the world requires
the support of our fellow believers. Slightly more ambiguous, though
suggestive, are the nearly tied answers to the question "What is missing for
you in your UU experience?" 52 percent said "greater intensity of
celebration, joy and spirituality." Celebration would seem to suggest
worship, about which the survey seems to reveal mixed feelings, but which I take
to be a fundamentally social experience. The word "spirituality" in
the answer, however, suggests otherwise, because we know that for Americans the
word spiritual often denotes private or personal experience whereas the word
religious denotes "institutional" religion. The second answer, which
garnered 49 percent of the most important category is "more racial and
cultural diversity and diversity of perspectives." The ambiguity here
lies in the fact that increasing diversity in any American institution requires
concerted social action-it's not something one can do all alone. On
the other hand valuing diversity for its own sake is highly compatible with
American individualism.
Looking for
resources from the history of the UU movement would require a degree of
specialized knowledge which I do not possess. But one place to start would
be to examine the writings of people like Henry W. Bellows, and other
institution builders that Conrad Wright has discussed. I'm sure that
would yield many interesting suggestions. I am even surer that the
writings of James Luther Adams are an invaluable treasure when it comes to a
social understanding of the Unitarian Universalist tradition.
However, as an
indication of where you currently are with respect to a social as opposed
to a radically individualist understanding of UUism, I would like to look at the
document Interdependence, particularly since in it coherent arguments are
presented, whereas survey results are like Rorschach tests that require a great
deal of problematic interpretation to understand. Interdependence sounds
its characteristic note from the first paragraph of its introduction where it
speaks of the "beloved community" as being at the center of Unitarian
Universalist belief. And then in the second paragraph it refers not only
to the UUA principle of "the interdependent web of existence," but to Jim
Adams's idea of "the covenant of being." (p. 1) Since I know Jim was
sympathetic to the theology of Paul Tillich (he dedicated The Prophethood of All
Believers to Tillich), as any religious liberal ought to be, I will return to
that idea of Being later on. Before the introduction ends, however, the
commission lays its cards on the table when it says "we are calling for a
paradigm shift from individualism to interdependence, from the autonomy of
congregations to a community of autonomous congregations." (p. 3) But
then in the next chapter the commission takes another giant step. In a
section headed "Toward a new doctrine of the church," there is the
subheading "Embracing the church universal," which is spelled out as
follows:
Unitarian
Universalism or the UU movement are not the ultimate locus of our religious
loyalty and commitment, because there are other religious bodies in North
America and around the world with whom we also enjoy some sense of community.
And beyond these organized religious bodies, there are myriad individuals, known
and unknown, whom we would include in any full accounting of "the church
universal." (p. 11)
And to make clear
the link between local congregation and universal church the document goes on to
say:
Through the
congregation, the individual enables the universal religious community to
become more than a nice idea; the individual enables it to become a historical
reality. Conversely, through the congregation , the universal religious
community calls the individual out of solitariness into solidarity with
social, natural, and spiritual realities that transcend the self. (p. 12)
But here, much as
I applaud the general sentiment, I still find the solitary individual understood
as somehow prior to community, the fatal error of all dissenting religion.
That limitation is almost but not quite transcended in a statement later on in
the document:
With our
tradition of autonomy comes a responsibility to the whole body. We have
tended to focus on our independence, but it is the relational aspects of our
common life that have the potential to transform us, bringing wholeness,
unity, and an experience of the holy that we seek. (p. 96)
In the dissenting
tradition the individual is primary and community, however valued, is secondary.
This gets into American culture in the widespread sentimental value attributed
to community by virtually all sectors of the American public except academics,
an exception it would take me too far afield to explain now. But this
voluntaristic notion of community, however treasured, is unable to bear the
weight it is expected to carry. This understanding of community is
perilous because individuals devote themselves to it only so long as it "meets
their needs," and when it doesn't, there is no claim of perseverance or
loyalty that community so understood, can exert. I am convinced that only
a social understanding of human nature is ontologically true and that only a
social ontology could divert American culture from the destructive course upon
which it seems to be set.
I am now ready to
move beyond the realm of sociological analysis into the realm of theology.
Here I want to issue a warning. Jim Adams in the old days when I was at
Harvard, used to call me at 11 o'clock at night and say "Bob, put up your
guard." He was about to ask me to do one more thing, and he told me to
put up my guard so he wouldn't coerce me into accepting another obligation,
and while I was putting up my guard he was slowly twisting my arm until I agreed
to do the one more thing. I have no capacity to do any arm-twisting
tonight, but still I say, put up your guard. Here comes a trinitarian
sacramentalist making suggestions for UU theology. Forewarned is
forearmed.
Let me start by
saying that the most depressing thing in the survey questionnaire to me was
question no. 18, "What do you expect to happen for you when you attend a UU
worship service?" The problem is that none of the five possible answers
have anything to do with worship as I understand it: not "get something
to help get me through the week," not "intellectual stimulation," not
"social interaction," not "remember with gratitude and celebrate what is
most important in my life (note in my life)," and not "music and community
singing," though I agree with Clark Olsen that the weak showing of the latter,
which I think has at least something to do with worship, is upsetting.
Worship as I
understand it is worship of something, and that defining aspect of worship
doesn't seem to be implied in any of the five answers. What I am
suggesting is that the absence of a social ontology is mirrored in the absence
in worship of symbolism of something that transcends the individual.
Indeed there is a wistful moment in the document Interdependence where that
truth seems to be recognized:
While discarding
the doctrine of Lordship, have we also lost a principle of union? Are we
in a community of congregations merely to simplify the delivery of services?
Does Unitarian Universalism have any meaning larger than what it means to any
particular congregation? (p. 18)
I want to suggest
in a minute the way in which Christian symbolism has what Jim Adams called
"community-forming power." (Interdependence, p. 12) But
first, to show you how ecumenical I am, I want to refer to Buddhism, Zen
Buddhism in particular. Some of you may know that I started out as a Japan
specialist, and that I have been not only professionally but personally
interested in Zen Buddhism, having some experience of Zen practice, and having
served for a year on the board of the San Francisco Zen Center. Talk abut
individualistic religion! American seekers have been drawn to Zen often
because of what they perceive as its total religious individualism. Just
to illustrate, let me give a quote from someone Steven Tipton interviewed for
his book Getting Saved from the Sixties:
I started Zen to
get something for myself, to stop suffering, to get enlightened.
Whatever it was, I was doing it for myself. I had hold of myself and I
was reaching for something. Then to do it, I found out I had to give up
that hold on myself. Now it has hold of me. . . (Berkeley:
UC Press, 1982, p. 115.)
One of the things
that surprised, and even annoyed, some seekers is that Zen practice is not just
sitting, it is also worship. As part of every zazen session there is a
worship service. The heart sutra is chanted and the Buddha and all the
teachers who link the students to the Buddha are not only remembered but
worshipped. Quite physically worshipped. One gets down on
one's knees repeatedly during the service and touches one's forehead to the
mat as one remembers those who made one's practice possible. Indeed one
of the purposes of the worship service is to remind one that one is able to
practice zazen only because of a community of practice that stretches back for
millennia, but also that, as Suzuki Roshi put it, "our practice is for
others." Buddhism, at least Mahayana Buddhism, is not, whatever
Westerners may think, individualistic. Its social ontology is absolute.
The Buddha nature is in every grain of dust, every tile, every animal, and
certainly in every human. We are all part of the dharma body, we all float
in the sea of dharma. Our little private selves are illusionary; in the
light of the Buddha nature they don't even exist.
Before I get more
specifically into Christian social symbolism, let me say that I don't think
that the theism that alarms humanists is even necessary for Christianity.
Paul Tillich, who defined god as "Being itself," was not, it is now
generally agreed, a theist, but a panentheist, and nonetheless one of the most
influential Christian theologians of the century. But for me, theology is
as much what we do as what we say, and it is what we say in connection with what
we do that is more important than what we say abstractly. So I want to
start with the sacraments, baptism and communion or Eucharist.
The dissenting
churches are characteristically suspicious of the sacraments-too closely
related to hierarchy and dogma-but in their suspicion they also give evidence
of their ontological individualism. For the sacraments give a tangible,
physical expression to the one body of which we are all members. Paul is
getting at this when he says in First Corinthians, "By one Spirit we are
baptized into one body-Jews or Greeks, slaves or free." In Galations
he adds, "male or female," and we might add, without violating the spirit of
Paul's letters, "black or white, Eastern or Western." In a
sacramental Christianity, our diversity and pluralism are penultimate goods and
we are right to celebrate them. But in the Spirit we become one body; that
is our ultimate good.
And in the
Eucharist the social ontology becomes if anything even more evident:
the Holy Spirit sanctifies the bread and the wine so that they become the body
and blood of Christ, and we, partaking of it, become members of the body of
Christ. In the Eucharist, the word becomes flesh; God becomes incarnate so
that we participate in the incarnate God; the priority of the body, the
communion of the saints which was here before us, will be here after us, and
upholds us every moment of out lives, is clearly asserted relative to our
individual selves. With our innate American anti-institutionalism we tend
to distance ourselves from the "institutional" church; we refer to "it"
or "them." But the Holy Spirit fills us; we are the church.
That's what Vatican II was saying about the people of God. The church is
not something over against us, any more than God is over against us. God
in Christ is with us; the Holy Spirit fills us; we are the church. At
least that is one possible Christian understanding. I suspect that most
American Christians, and not in the dissenting traditions alone, have a much
more individualistic understanding of their own faith. It is interesting
to me that your own Jim Adams expressed, toward the end of The Prophethood of
All Believers a deeply social understanding of the church:
The church as a
community of faith and hope is entrusted in a special way with the ministry of
wholeness for the individual and the society, for each member individually and
all together. The church is, then the messenger of hope for the kingdom
which through God's grace is always "at hand," available. (Beacon,
1986, p. 310)
My point, after
all, is not to sell you any bill of goods, Buddhist or Christian. My point
is in the end sociological: that without powerful rituals and
sacraments-practices that make our beliefs tangible, physical-and without
the powerful symbols and narratives that resonate with those rituals and
sacraments, the fundamental truth of social ontology can be covered over.
We may begin to really believe that we have created ourselves out of nothing,
that our selves are, as Robert Coles put it, "the only or main form of
reality." (Habits, p. 143)
Beneath the
surface glitter of American culture there is a deep inner core, which, I have
argued, is ultimately religious: the sacredness of the conscience of every
single individual. Nothing I have said tonight takes away from the
enormous power for good of that idea. It is responsible for the best in
our culture. But, by the very weakness of any idea of human solidarity
associated with it in a culture dominated by the dissenting Protestant
tradition, it opens the door to the worst in our culture. It easily leads
to the idea that humans are nothing but self-interest maximizers, and devil take
the hindmost. It is that version that we see all around us. I
don't think we can challenge that version until we come to see that the
sacredness of the individual depends ultimately on our solidarity with all
being, not on the vicissitudes of our private selves. You face in your
very denomination the most basic conundrum of American life. If you can
solve it you may help lead the larger society out of the wilderness into which
it has wandered.
return
to Lectures
|